Basic concepts |
Pedagogics
Part 2
2.3.2   THE REALITY OF EDUCATING
2.3.2.1   The relationships: reality, life reality, life world, educative realtiy
The reality of educating in all of the places it appears can be found only in the world where persons live. Thus, it is present in the life
world and can only be seen there. Consequently, the reality of educating is characterized as being grounded (rooted, embedded) in the
life world and this means that it possesses anthropological status. In other words, pronouncements about Anthropos (human
beings) can have relevance for understanding the reality of educating; that is, there are anthropological categories that have
pedagogical meaning. These pedagogical meanings, for epistemological purposes (illuminating with the aim of acquiring and broadening
knowledge), are called pedagogical categories.22
However, it is not only human beings that live. There also is animal and plant life. That is, the life world is an aspect of a larger life reality. Together, human life and the other forms of living constitute life reality. However, as soon as a human being attributes meaning to these forms of living he makes them part of his life world.
The reality of educating is placed in the life world and the life world is a facet of life reality that exists next to and with non-living reality
as a reality of things. Together, the world of things and life constitute reality and a human being (especially a thinker) is attuned to
learning to know this comprehensive reality. Since this reality is particularly complex, a person usually selects an aspect of it to study.
Thus, a pedagogue selects the aspect known as educating for phenomenological and philosophy of life approaches. The reality of
educating, in its various places of appearance, is subjected to scientifically necessary and philosophy of life permissible steps of thinking
in order to disclose pedagogically meaningful ways of living (pedagogical essences). He does this with the aim of an ontological
understanding of the reality of educating, ultimately for the benefit of the child-in-education.
2.3.2.2   Places where the reality of educating appear
The reality of educating, as such, is the source of knowledge about itself. Anyone who wants to acquire knowledge about educating
approaches that reality, itself, in order to disclose its real essences. If one wants to determine which ways of living are meaningful to
educating (accompanying a child), he searches for them in the reality of educating itself.
A question that now arises is where the reality of educating can be found so it can be investigated. This is a question about the places it appears.
In the pages that follow, an explication is given of the following places of appearance:
The everyday reality of educating is characterized by a vague directedness to educative and learning aims. This vagueness can make
the essence analysis (as disclosing pedagogically meaningful ways of living) difficult. The vague directedness takes many forms that
the essence thinker (meaning discloser) must be aware of
Another possibility is to look at the pedagogic effects in the everyday reality of educating. This means there is a search for
particular results, namely, if the educand, as subject (person), perceives the pedagogic-as-such and responds to it. Has he
perceived the pedagogic and assimilated it?28 One way to find an answer to this question is to attend to the
educand’s perspective on the reality of educating with which he is involved. This can be done by analyzing his commentary
about his being with adults. In this way, light can be thrown on the pedagogical essentials because the educand is always a participant
in their reality. Which ways of living are seen by the educand as pedagogically meaningful, thus as supportive of him in his being on the
way to proper adulthood? Possible pedagogical essences that are laid bare in this way can then be verified by the pedagogician with his
phenomenological steps of thinking. Because the educand is not yet adult, along with his non-purposeful reflection on education, the
pedagogical essentials possibly (but not necessarily) will be more hidden in his commentary than that of the adults (educators and
pedagogues) might be.29
Another way to investigate pedagogic results with the aim of disclosing essences and verifying their essence status is to make a study
of educator commentary about educating. In this connection, F. Bernard,30 a D. Ed. student of the
author, has done excellent research. From this research it is clear that educator (here mother) commentary about educating in
unmistakable ways serves the verification of essence status.
The status of the everyday reality of educating can be described as the status it has because of the particular position it holds, i.e., the
position of the primary point of departure. What is meant by this?
In answering this question, it is especially the explications of C. K. Oberholzer that are insightful. The following statements are
meaningful in this respect:
To take the everyday reality of educating as point of departure leads to working in scientifically accountable ways indeed in the sense that there is a beginning where the evident facts of this reality in their original ways of appearing come to light.
M. J. Langeveld, in his reference to the pedagogic situation notices, among other things: “There we find activities, there we find thinking
about its origin and point of focus … And no theory is worthy of us and this situation … This situation is not something that we can
devise while at our desk or infer from some nice theory; it is living itself … Children develop this way and that, one says. But I ask you,
how do you know? By looking in a glass retort? or by means of human educating? Ah exactly, but then why do not you begin there? …
and you should never be afraid to go there and investigate the empirical where it has its origin.”37
Faithfulness to reality to which particular scientific value is attributed requires that the logically obvious primary point of departure be
taken, i.e., there where educating occurs and thus there where pedagogically meaningful ways of living definitely are found. The reality
of educating forces itself on the pedagogician as the most meaningful point of departure for his thinking about the pedagogic.
Literature as a particular place of the appearance the
pedagogic action must not be overlooked. It has already been
indicated that pedagogical essences appear in the
family novel38 and in the family drama.39 The reason such
non-scientific and non-philosophical pronouncements as these
about the essentials are not considered pedagogically
is because they do not form a logically consistent whole.40 The
question now is how the pedagogical meaningfulness of
pronouncements about educating in literature can be
determined. A meaningful way would be to
subject such pronouncements to the phenomenological steps
of thinking. The pronouncements that have passed this
verification are then already contents of the pedagogical and
must be further ordered into a logically consistent whole.
In the novel (and also the drama, poem and short story)
particular meanings are present. Phenomenology discloses the
how and what of these meanings and primarily involves a
becoming aware of them; it also identifies the
essential moments in the novel, etc. It is these moments
that have ontic-ontological status that are sought.4141 The
phenomenological steps of thinking are applied to determine
the ontic-ontological status of the pedagogically meaningful
ways of living that appear in the family novel, etc. Another
method is to compare these essences with an essence table
constructed from already verified essences. This is the
method followed by Jubelius and by Swanepoel.
In this connection, e.g., Jubelius notes: “the study of a number
of novels in which educative situations are depicted in the
normal course of circumstances can serve as a verification of
whether the already described pedagogical essences are life
realities or not …. It is not adequate for a phenomenologist to
depend only upon the phenomenon or to enrich his
experience by observing another’s. Use also must be made
of other means of verification that give fundamental insight
into the structure of human existence, and here the novel is of
invaluable worth.”42 E. M. Swanepoel finds: “In the seventeen
dramas studied the dramatists continually showed how the
children who suffered defects in the essences of growing up
after that continually pined, sometimes to such an extent
that they did not become proper adults but were themselves
forced to live in an illusive world. In the dramas where the
essences indeed were indicated, the children grew up in the
embrace of parental love.”43
It is clear that ignoring literature as a place of appearance of
the reality of educating will lead to an impoverishment in
understanding educating.
The pedagogician who takes the everyday reality of educating
as his primary point of departure for his pedagogical
thinking, thus also for applying his phenomenological steps of
thinking, in spite of careful application of the steps of
thinking, still runs the risk that the pedagogical essences
he discloses can merely be rational constructions, thus
mere intellectual creations that have no quality of reality. In
this context, literature (novel, short story, drama, poem) that
deals with the family situation can serve as verification. This
means that particular verification status can be attributed to
literature. In this regard, the following conclusions of Jubelius
and Swanepoel are meaningful:
“In studying the nine novels the pedagogic essences are
disclosed in such a striking way that there can be no doubt
that the essences indeed constitute an essential part of an
authentic educative situation. The analysis of the novels has
shown without a doubt and in a striking way that the
fundamental pedagogic essences have reality status in the life
world and cannot be viewed as mere constructions of rational
thought.”
“This study of the dramas in which the pedagogic essences
showed themselves so clearly is proof that the essences are
life world realities. This completely refutes the assertion that
they are merely rational constructions. The dramas
indeed served as essence verification, and to such an extent
that they once again underlined and emphasized the
importance and necessity of the pedagogic structures and
essences for successful educative activities.”
Thus, literature has a particular status because of its characteristic of “verification of reality status” and this occurs by showing that the
pedagogical essences are not merely constructions of thinking that do not consider the reality of educating itself. If in studying
literature possible pedagogical essences come to the attention of the pedagogician that he had not seen in the everyday reality of
educating, it is advisable to follow the phenomenological steps of thinking with such essences in order to verify their essence status in
scientifically accountable and philosophy of life permissible ways.
In the social sciences46 often pronouncements about
educating are found that rightly must be verified by the
pedagogician. Pedagogically meaningful pronouncements
that come to his attention in this way must be ordered into a
logically consistent whole to become pedagogic contents.
The pedagogician is inclined (and rightly so) to have
certain requirements for those social sciences he deems
worthy of taking knowledge from with his essence disclosing
and essence status verifying. His scientific practice is
essentially applied phenomenology and therefore is
preeminently anti-naturalistic47 and anti-Marxist.4848 Thus, the
pedagogician will at least demand that the psychology from
which he will take knowledge, from an autonomous
pedagogical perspective, will be a phenomenologi
psychology, phenomenological sociology, etc. He knows
beforehand that naturalistic and Marxist (i.e., neo-Marxist)
talk about the reality of educating will have little or no chance
of being relevant to his essence disclosing and essence status
verifying. Here there is mention of a strong phenomenological
bias especially against naturalism and Marxism.
The pedagogician will involve himself with a psychology and
sociology that at least meets the following requirements:
Under certain conditions the social sciences warrant the
pedagogician’s attention. The reality of educating, as it
appears for these sciences, can serve as a verification of the
reality status of pedagogically meaningful ways of living
(pedagogical essences) that are found in the everyday reality
of educating and thus determine whether the essences that are
phenomenologically disclosed by the pedagogican are not
merely thought-constructions that have nothing to do with the
reality of educating.
It is even possible that in these sciences potential pedagogical
essences appear that have not yet been noticed by
pedagogicians. Such possible pedagogical essences will then
be verified by him through his phenomenological steps of
thinking in order to determine their real essence status.
That philosophical anthropology has the possibility of
making meaningful pronouncements justified by
pedagogic verification appears so from the following
quotation: “ Philosophical anthropology, as a regional
ontology, involves itself with the primordial given
of being human as becoming human whenever the task is seen
as a hermeneutics of the onticity being human as
becoming ….”51 Among other things, philosophical
anthropology concerns itself with explicating the fact that
being human also shows itself as becoming a person.
Educating as assistance in becoming52 is a particular way
of giving support to this becoming53 and pedagogics is the
science of this event. Consequently, philosophical-
anthropological prouncements have the possibility of being
pedagogically meaningful.
Child anthropology, as a form of philosophical anthropology,
will further investigate what being a child really and
essentially is as a form of being human, i.e., it will interpret
child life within the whole of the image of being human54 apart
from the aims with the child in such a way that an un-childlike
image of a child from which the child is absent is avoided.
Pronouncements about the essences of child being as an
expression of a child’s being human must necessarily catch the
attention of the pedagogician and definitely call him to verify
them pedagogically. He applies his phenomenological steps of
thinking to determine the pedagogic meaningfulness of such
pronouncements. This means that a philosophical
anthropology in which no child, no family, no personal past
and future, no activity that is described as “educating” can be
anticipated can have no relevance for the pedagogician.55
In this there appears nothing that justifies verification by his steps
of thinking.
Ethics is a science that concerns itself with a person’s
“appearing as ethical-existential subjectivity, i.e., his existence
as a normative-norm-using being.”56 The child is a becoming
subject who lives and is ethical-existential, normative-norm-
using. Pedagogics is the normative science57 of educating that
is a being concerned with the child in normativity.58 Thus,
there are particular points of contact between ethics and
peagogics that ethical pronouncements warrant pedagogical
verification. Possible meaningful ways of living that are
disclosed by ethics are subjected to the pedagogician’s
verifying steps of thinking , followed by a logically consistent
ordering.
In light of the above it is now asserted that there can be
mention of:
The reality of educating indeed can be observed from these
perspectives in the life world. The pedagogician then verifies
these appearances to determine whether his own disclosures
of pedagogical essences by his phenomenological approach to
the everyday reality of educating are real pedagogical essences
with anthropological status and not mere rational
constructions without taken into account this reality.
If possible pedagogically meaningful ways of living are
disclosed by these perspectives that have not yet been brought
to light by the pedagogue himself, he can subject them to his
phenomenological steps of thinking in order to determine
their essence status.
|